WHY EVEN CONTEMPLATE CHANGING EMPLOYMENT STATUS
BLOG
187
WHY EVEN CONTEMPLATE CHANGING EMPLOYMENT STATUS?
I hope that both the ICAEW and the CIOT
are going to strongly oppose the proposals in the government recent issued
“Employment Status Consultation”. This
has ostensibly been issued to work out how to give effect to the proposals made
by the Taylor Review of Modern Working Practices. The government have said that they accept all
of the Review’s recommendations except in relation to tax. Tax was actually specifically excluded from
Mr Taylor’s terms of reference but he considered it just the same. The consultation document was issued by the
Department for Business etc, but is jointly badged by them with H M Treasury
and HMRC.
It says very little about tax – two
pages on Alignment between tax and rights – but that is why it is so
dangerous. The likelihood is that HMRC
will piggy-back onto its conclusions.
The real problem is that it starts from
the wrong place, so its conclusions are bound to be flawed. It suggests giving statutory effect to the
principle laid down by the Courts. While
acknowledging that will result in a loss of flexibility, it suggests that is a
fair trade off against clarity and certainty.
That may be right, but it should not be overlooked that inflexibility
can, and often does, result in unfairness, so it is not reasonable to ignore
(as the consultation does) that certainty and fairness rarely make good
bedfellows. Certainty caters for the
norm. The unfairnesses arise from
abnormal cases. Furthermore, Courts do
not “lay down principles”. They
interpret the law in the context of the specific facts before them. The Courts are accordingly fundamentally
flexible in the sense that a different set of facts may well produce a
different nuance on the principles discerned by the Court.
But that is not my real concern. It starts, as any test of employment status
must do, with the statement by MacKenna J in the 1968 Ready Mixed Concrete
Social Security case. “The servant
agrees that, in consideration of a wage or other remuneration, he will provide
his own work and skill in the performance of some service for his
master. He agrees, expressly or
impliedly, that in the performance of that service he will be subject to the
other’s control in a sufficient degree to make that other master. The other provisions of the contract
are consistent with its being a contract of service”. (The underlining is from the consultation
document; note particularly that nothing in the third sentence is underlined).
It there infers “This has developed into
the following main characteristics –
·
Mutuality of
obligation …
·
Control …
·
Personal
service …
If these three characteristics are
present, the Courts will then consider other criteria relevant to the case that
are consistent with a contract of employment or service”.
Tax specialists will know that this is
indeed how HMRC like to interpret the cases.
Can we find control and personal service (mutuality of obligation means
no more than there is consideration so as to make the arrangement a contract)? If we can, it is an employment unless you can
show a good reason why it is not. But
MacKenna J’s test is not “control”; it is “control in a sufficient degree to
make that other master”. In other words
it is looking for a master/servant relationship.
The way the two Courts seem nowadays to
be interpreting MacKenna J is that there is a two-part test. Is there mutuality of obligation, a
master/servant relationship and an obligation to personally perform the
service? If so, the arrangement is
capable of being an employment; if not, it cannot be an employment. If the arrangement passes test 1, test 2 is
to look at the facts, untramelled by test 1, and ask whether or not the facts
are consistent with employment.
This is not hair-splitting. It is fundamental. The consultation document test does not
clarify Court decisions; it usurps them.
Before looking more closely at why control per se is the wrong test, it
is helpful to pose the question as to why does the distinction between
employment and self-employment matter.
The answer is that it doesn’t for most of us. I do not care whether my dentist’s
receptionist is employed or self-employed; I only care that she makes my
appointments. I do not care whether my
gardener is employed or self-employed; I only care that he keeps my garden trim.
I do not care if my electrician is
employed or self-employed; I only care that he procures that my electricity
supply functions.
The only reason it matters is that the
State has created a distinction – or rather, a number of different
distinctions. The question therefore
ought to be whether those distinctions, most of them created the best part of a
century or more ago, are either still necessary or the right distinctions in
modern society. To look at how to define
the distinction is treating the symptoms, not the disease.
The State has drawn a distinction in
three distinct areas, employment rights, welfare rights and tax. But in all three it has drawn the dividing
line in a different place, so it is unsurprising that the categories of people
who are not self-employed should differ between the three. Introducing a common test of employment
cannot therefore work unless the line is drawn in the same place for all three,
which requires the State to revisit the reason why the line is where it is.
I am not an historian (albeit that I
know a fair amount about the history of tax) but I think it is fairly clear why
the lines were drawn as they are. In the
19th and early 20th century some employers exploited
their workers mercilessly. The State
cannot let people starve on the street.
Accordingly if a worker can be dismissed peremptorily or is not paid or
paid a pittance, the State has to pick up the slack. Workers’ rights ensure that workers are
treated fairly and that the costs of doing so are borne by the employer, not
the State. Social Security in the
Beveridge era was insurance based.
Everyone would pay into a common fund and be paid out of that fund when
in need. The problem with that is that
the self-employed do not have regular income so cannot be expected to make
regular contributions. Accordingly for
an insurance-based system to work, they could insure for long-term benefits
(pensions and health) but had to be excluded from short-term benefits
(unemployment, maternity, etc) where Beveridge based entitlement to benefit on
short-term insurance contributions. Tax
started from capacity. Initially
employees were not taxed. Only the
self-employed and, later, office holders paid tax. It was only when an effective way could be
found to tax employees that they were brought into the tax net.
It is therefore unsurprising that the
tax line was drawn between the employed and the self-employed but when it came
to welfare, it was accepted that was the wrong place to draw the line. The Employment Rights Act 1996 confers rights
not only on employees but also on workers, which it defines as “the individual
undertakes to do or perform personally any work or services for another party
to the contract whose status is not by virtue of the contract that of a client
or customer of any profession or undertaking carried on by the
individual”. This recognises that a
person can perform personal services for another and yet be neither an employee
nor a business owner. It assimilates the
worker with an employee whereas the tax law assimilates the worker with the
self-employed. Again, unsurprising, as
the employment laws wants to pass responsibilities to others so as to prevent
workers having to be supported by the State.
The impetus for both the consultation
document and the Taylor review is of course the growth of the “gig
economy”. This creates self-employed
workers whose business is limited by reference to the needs of their major (or
generally only) customer. This generally
means that the worker/businessman does not need a business organisation as his
customer carries out his business for him.
Even that is not new. The
aspiring pop singer of the 1960s or 1980s who signed a record contract was in a
similar position.
What is new is that people are today
telling self-employed people that they are being exploited by not being offered
employment. But being treated
differently is not exploitation. No one
is forced to be self-employed. Of course
if one wants to cycle around London all Summer the chances of getting employed
to do so are very limited.
Self-employment as a courier is the only real option. But no-one is forced to be a courier
either. A person who does not want to be
self-employed can find employment in the retail food industry fairly
readily. Why should a person who chooses
an occupation that entails self-employment expect to be treated differently to
any other self-employed person?
Even that is perhaps the wrong
question. A better one is probably that
if the State wishes to provide benefits to a large number of self-employed
persons who work mainly for a single customer, why should that prompt a change
in the definition of employment? It is
far more sensible to create a category of quasi-self-employed people and to decide
what rights that category should be entitled to and legislate to provide such
rights. This has never been a problem in
the past. For example, at one stage the
then government decided that actors ought to have the National Insurance
benefit applicable to employees. They
did so by deeming actors to be employees for NIC purposes; they did not change
the definition of employment but left actors accepting the remaining
disadvantages of self-employment.
Of course every status has both
advantages and disadvantages. The Taylor
Committee looked almost wholly at the disadvantages of the gig economy. But for many workers in it the advantages –
in particular flexibility – are far more important than Mr Taylor’s perceived
disadvantages. Re-drawing the line to
turn such people into either employees or workers could well result in a loss
of those disadvantages, as the administrative costs of calculating employment
or workers’ rights for flexible workers may well make the use of such people
uneconomic.
ROBERT
MAAS
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home